THE PRINCIPLE OF TENABILITY

A statement is tenable when both l) there is adequate evidence that its assertion is in accordance with the state of affairs to which it refers
and
2) its expression is not misleading to its recipients


By 'tenability' is here meant the judgement that any statement is likely to be true. It is therefore necessary to discuss the relation between tenability and truth, which corresponds to that between belief and knowledge. When something is known with certainty we call it 'true'. If something is not known with certainty, yet there are grounds for believing it to be true, we call it 'tenable'. The concept of tenability is useful in allowing us to avoid the problem of what is definitively known to be true. For example, regard the following:-

"Failure to negotiate a total world ban on nuclear weapons will eventually lead to the use of such weapons in warfare"

One cannot say whether the above is true or false, obviously. Instead one can judge (believe) that it will hold true or that it will not... or else one can reserve judgement as to its te
nability. To judge it tenable one would require arguments stating grounds for the likelihood of its becoming true, which must be stronger arguments than those one could discover against the likelihood of its holding true. This is what is meant by the term "adequate evidence" in the principle above.

So tenability or untenability stand for judgements about any statement made by an individual on the basis of 'subjective' experience or on the basis of what is commonly agreed and is judged as likely to be true by that individual. Such a judgement is an assessment of the probability of the statement proving to be true/when conclusive investigation of the relevant state of affairs or circumstances can be made. It does not involve mere belief, such as a guess in the dark, but a genuine assessment of available evidence. One may thus speak of degrees of tenability, high or low likelihood of the truth/falsity of a statement, but only in special cases can tenability or untenability meaningfully be quantified, such as in fields-of study which lend themselves to statistical analysis and the application of probability theory. In respect of practical life where the issues are very often broad and of a general nature, there is seldom grounds for more than the rough distinctions between 'low', 'medium' and 'high' tenability.

The first requirement of the principle of tenability is that there is adequate evidence that an assertion is in accordance with the state of affairs to which it refers, this makes it clear that only statements that refer to potentially observable conditions can be judged tenable (i.e. those later to be defined here as 'descriptive' statements). How one organises evidence and assesses what is adequate for the judgement of tenability/untenability is a subject dealt with under a subsequent chapter entitled "Ordered surveys of arguments on an issue". The first requirement of the principle refers mainly to factual or 'scientific' evidence, in the broadest sense of scientific.

The second requirement, that the expression is not misleading to its recipients, is pragmatical/semantical rather than strictly scientific or logical, in that it deals with the conditions of the communication of truth, rather than the assessment of it. One cannot call a statement tenable if the expression used is misleading, biased or tendentious. Thus the second requirement deals with the communication of information about states of affairs, such as statements in reported accounts of factual events, in giving evidence or first-hand witness accounts. Under this also come statements made in resume of texts or of the stated views of other persons and groups. The principle can also be stated negatively, that is to say, formulating what constitutes a break of the principle as follows:


A statement about any state of affairs is untenable when both 1) there is adequate evidence that its assertion is not sufficiently in accordance with the state of affairs to which it refers, and 2) its expression is misleading to its recipients


Reports by first-hand observers


Firstly, when an expression that makes a report on an actual state of affairs is misleading, it will seldom be sufficiently clear and cognitive to give an accurate description of that to which it refers. This will also mean that one or more of the other principles of efficient communication are broken. In practice, an infringement of the principle of tenability occurs when the recipient(s) of the report misinterpret the expression and thus also the state of affairs itself. The sources of such misinterpretation therefore can include the use of emotive language, of insufficiently appropriate or precise expressions, of inconciseness and contradictions in terms, all of which have been exemplified earlier. Whether the expression conforms to prevailing language usage in the situation that applies, depends upon opinions as to what are sufficiently neutral and appropriate terms in the instances involved.

Where a first-hand report consists in a sequence of expressions, misinterpretation can arise from incorrect ordering of the expressions, confusing the recipient as to the actual sequence of events reported.
Eg) Consider the great difference between:-
EO Thereafter the demonstrators used physical violence against the police, who unfortunately shot two of the demonstrators.
E1 Unfortunately the police shot two of the demonstrators, who thereafter used physical violence against the police.

There are so many ways in which a first-hand report can be misleading due to language factors that no thorough list is attempted here. The following, however, can be regarded as a special - but most common - case of being misleading... namely, by inadequate representation of facts.

Secondly, when an assertion is not sufficiently in accordance with the facts, it may be partially correct as a description of a state of affairs, but simply not true as a whole. On the other hand-however, it may be practically impossible to verify or refute with certainty. Though we. referred to insufficiency of the assertion in representing a state of affairs, rather than only its being false, statements for or against which no evidence can be found cannot reasonably be judged as to their tenability or untenability.
For example: "Richard Milhous Nixon secretly wrote graffiti on toilet walls." This statement, as far as available evidence goes, can neither be judged tenable nor untenable. One cannot thereby exclude its tenability or its untenability if evidence should later be forthcoming.

In evaluating the degree of tenability or untenability of a statement the expression must be interpreted as to its exact meaning, to what state of affairs it refers. Quite often the assertion one derives from the expression will depend upon the interpreters own prior acquaintance with such states of affairs - or even the particular one in question. The interpreter's prior knowledge of relevant facts can sometimes be crucial in deciding how to interpret the expression or decide precisely to what it refers, nonetheless, only when a definite assertion is understood can its truth or falsity be considered. So in the final review, the judgement as to degree of tenability or otherwise is a separate decision that follows after the decision as to its correct interpretation,

The evidence necessary to establish untenability will depend entirely upon other sources than the statement in question. These may include personal observation) investigation of secondary evidence such as other witnesses' reports, texts, and recordings of all types and even experiment. No lists of the ways of collecting control evidence can be made, so ingeniously varied are the methods of investigation used in all the areas of human enterprise. Yet since we are dealing with reports by first-hand observers, there will in all cases be some actual state(s) of affairs upon which the truth or falsity of the report depends, even where the report is entirely faked. In such cases the falsity of a report is demonstrated by reference to other states of affairs that did occur.

Where an alleged state of affairs no longer pertains, of course, investigation must rely upon circumstantial evidence and reasoning. This is invariably the method used in dealing with reports about alleged human motives or intentions at all events, for the intended meaning of human acts cannot be observed or properly demonstrated other than by indirect, circumstantial evidence.

Reports almost always contain more than one expression so that the possibilities of untenability of the report as a whole are increased. It can be affected by whatever is chosen as a headline or paragraph heading, by the ordering of information in different sequences, the size of print used for various parts, the placing of the material around photographic or other graphic material that can 'colour' the report and so on. When judging the tenability of a report as a whole, not only should each statement be studied, but also the possibility of crucial information or facts being omitted so as to alter the tenability of what is explicitly stated.

Third, when an expression in a report tends to favour the viewpoint on a state of affairs of one concerned party to the neglect of that of another concerned party it is tendentious. In other words, the report is biased and as such cannot be judged as making a highly tenable statement. Since there is a party to the matter (or perhaps more than one other party) which finds its view disfavoured, it is likely that the facts are not sufficiently well-established. All tendentious statements are not untenable however, for either party may be in the wrong. Only a further assessment of evidence or factual study will decide the issue of tenability. This occurs frequently in broadcasting media and the daily press by the omission of information that would affect the receivers' judgement of its tenability, as can also be seen by the incompatible and conflicting reports that occur in publications of different political leanings. Purposive tendentiousness by the communicator is often very hard to prove satisfactorily, therefore one can only judge as to the likelihood of it having a tendentious effect upon the recipient's derived assertion (i.e. its interpreter's understanding of it).


Reports rendering the views of others


This is a special case of first-hand reports. Others' views are reported in shortened or compressed form for many purposes, of course, and the reasons for so doing as well as all the communicational circumstances will influence what it is reasonable to include in, detail or to present in resumé form. The principle of tenability is, more specifically, broken in these cases where the views of others are represented so as to alter a recipient's judgement of the tenability of those views. The originator's views constitute the state of affairs described, whether in spoken or written form. Statements of reporters about these can alter their tenability both because of the expressions chosen and the assertions conveyed. As this distinction has already been dealt with in general above, the following list of typical cases of misreporting does not distinguish between the meaning and truth of the statements,


General cases of misreporting others' views


a) Misquoting when directly reporting a statement verbatim.
b) Making the originator's views less precise so as to open for interpretations that are incorrect.
c) Making original statements more general where they were specific, thus altering their meaning to affect their tenability.
d) Presenting statements out of context so that the originator's qualifications of them are lost.
e) Omitting important points from the stated viewpoint of the originator.
f) Mixing reported views with the reporter's own comments or other materials so as to confuse recipients as to the originator's position.
g) Drawing implications from the originator's stated view that the originator might not accept as valid, without making clear that such implications are not also explicitly held by the originator.